Over the holiday period (which I count as the entirety of January, as my wedding took place on the 11th January, and I have not seriously returned to work until very recently) I read Why Marx was Right by Terry Eagleton. The book was given to me by my father– over in Italy from New Zealand for the aforementioned wedding– as he had gone out and bought it after I had sent my dissertation prospectus to the family group chat, a document that makes clear that Marx's thought is a very major focus in my current work.
I hadn't heard of the book before, and was delighted to discover what I think is a very accessible introduction to many of the key aspects of Marx's thought that drew and draw me to it. Indeed, I wish that I had known about the book when putting together the syllabus for my class on Marx last semester (discussed in the first section here), as it guides the reader towards the salient aspects of why Marx remains relevant without assuming that they have already laboured through Capital. Now that I do, it has become the gateway drug of choice when I am accosted with the by-now-seemingly-age-old question, dredged up equally often in non-academic and academic discussions regarding the focus of my dissertation; 'but why study Marx'?
Each chapter in Eagleton's delectable little book takes a misconception about Marx head on, explaining why it is unfounded. The wikipedia page does an excellent job of outlining the lines of argumentation in summative depth, so I'll just bullet them here:
Needless to say, as the sanguinely simple title of Eagleton's book implies, all of these allegations are unfounded at best; and, more likely, just plain wrong. It is, in fact, astonishing how relevant Marx's thought remains today, given how much political and historical distance there is between us and him. Indeed, we live in wake of an executive order given by a popularly elected president of the U.S. to root out 'Marxist equity'; and I will continue to argue that concieving clearly both of what such equity would look like if it were to appear is some of the most important scholarly work that, if philosophy and critical thinking is to remain a valued part of organized society, for which we should carve out space and time at universities, even as the capitalist assault on the enduring value of critical thought intensifies (t)here.
Eagleton's book is not just an accessible introduction, however. Its footnotes are concise yet sharp, pointed the more interested reader towards secondary literature and sections of Marx's ouevre that deserve closer attention. The influence of Fourier on Marx's political philosophy of utopia, for example, is a connection that I intend to follow up on in the coming months, having as it may interesting ramifications in the course of my study on what mathematical contours exist in Capital and Marx's other works. Balibar's book Philosophy of Marx– which I had bulleted on my lists, but have still not yet read– is also mentioned for Balibar's characterization of Marx as an antiphilosopher; a nomination that accords with my continually reinforced conception of Marx as one of the great masters of suspicion.
There are also some comments in the book that help me to carve out space to concieve of Marx's system as a philosophy (or anti-philosophy, perhaps) of the subject. (No doubt this is the terrain that Balibar will cover in that book, when I finally come around to reading it.) In the chapter on why Marx is not a crude materialist (chapter 6), for example, Eagleton cleverly shows how it is really capitalist 'philosophy' that is culpable of painting everything simply 'as it is', leaving no space for an imagination otherwise. (This being the source of Fred Jameson's / Mark Fisher's quip that 'it is easier to imagine the end of the world than it is the end of capitalism') The unfreedom of imagination otherwise in capitalism, Eagleton argues, is a feature and not a bug for that system's zombified reproduction:
The prejudice that thought is independent of reality is itself shaped by social reality. (Eagleton 2011, 135)
It is not too far to go from this claim to the insight that consumed the working life of Alfred Sohn-Rethel, for which I quote from my prospectus:
Though Sohn-Rethel is best known for coining the phrase 'real abstraction' (principally popularized by way of its mention in Adorno's Negative Dialectics (Adorno 2014)), the radical claim on which his sole philosophical monograph, Intellectual and Manual Labor, rests is this: "Exchange abstraction is not thought, but it has the form of thought" (Sohn-Rethel 1978, 99). The idea that there is a formal relation between the transcendental subject ("thought") and the political economy, i.e. the structure of a set of social relations that cannot necessarily be simply reduced to the sum of conscious operations of its constituents, situates Marx in a mathematical-philosophical lineage with which he is not always directly associated.
Marx's work, as Eagleton recognizes, is not just a sociological, historically-specific treatise on the unjust structure of nascent capitalism in the 19th century; though it is certainly that. It is also ``a theory of how historical animals function" (Eagleton 2011, 158), which is to say, a philosophy of the (human) subject, a serious reckoning with whether or not there is anything philosophical (trans-historical) that can be said about society, or whether we are doomed to never be justified in abstracting from a specific time and a specific place, wherein not only is the map not the territory, but the map is never anything useful or justified at all.